Public Law
Resources
Click on the tabs below to view the content for each book.
Questions & Answers
The Good, the Fair and the Ugly
Good essays are the gateway to top marks. The Good, The Fair, and The Ugly shows you the style of essay which works well in exams, as well as the simple errors that can cost you essential marks. Written by our Q&A authors, each of these interactive essay-based tutorials highlights key themes and common errors and illustrates essays of specific standards:
Whilst marking criteria will vary, as a general guide, the Good answer will be based on a general mark of a first or upper second class; the Fair answer will be based on a lower second or third class and the Ugly answer would result in a fail.
The Good
A number of commentators have argued that, in the only meaningful sense of the word, the UK has no constitution. Do you agree, and has this remained true following devolution to Scotland and the Human Rights Act 1998?
The claim that the UK has no constitution was originally put forward by Bryce, but has recently been forcefully expanded and restated by Ridley ((1988) 41 Parlt Aff 340). (1) Good use of relevant academic authority - the question invites students to display their knowledge of various academic writings on the UK 'constitution'. In essence, it distinguishes a merely descriptive definition of a constitution as that body of rules and arrangements that regulates the government of a country and its relations with its citizens from what is argued to be the more important one, which Ridley believes has been in use since the American War of Independence and the French Revolution and in which the word has a much more specialised and normative meaning. Under this approach, he argues, there are four particular characteristics which a constitution must have. This essay will consider these characteristics, but will also discuss some more basic characteristics, which, it will be argued, a constitution must possess and which are not expressly mentioned by Ridley. This combined set of characteristics will then be used as a measure against which to judge the existence or non-existence of the UK Constitution. The final part of the essay will examine whether the introduction of devolution and the (at least, partial) incorporation of the ECHR via the HRA changes the conclusions previously reached on the UK Constitution. (2) A brief introduction setting out the structure of the essay demonstrates to the examiner that the student has understood the parameters of the question - a frequent problem in student essays.
It is suggested that there are perhaps two essential characteristics or purposes of constitutions, at least as they are understood within the tradition of liberal democracy to which Ridley refers. The first is that constitutions are necessary in order to control the power of the State; the second is that constitutions ensure that the power of the State derives from a legitimate source. As to the first notion, constitutions may be seen to exercise such control in a number of ways. As Schauer has pointed out (Playing by the Rules, 1991, pp 118–120), they are power-allocating (3) It can be effective to use academics to set up a point and then argue further – this demonstrates that the student has understood the argument, as the question requires. : they usually distribute power amongst the different organs of government, according to law. This represents a limitation on State power in two ways. First, and more basically, there is a formal limitation; allocation of power in this way means that power may not be exercised arbitrarily by any part of government that finds it convenient to do so, but only by that organ of government which is authorised, and publicly authorised at that, to do so. This, in the simplest sense, is the idea of limited government, or government under law. Ridley does not expressly identify this as an essential aspect of a constitution, but it is submitted that this notion of power-allocation through law is implicit in his first characteristic of a constitution, that it ‘establishes’ the system of government.
The second aspect of power-allocation is rather more substantive: allocation should offer a more concrete guarantee against tyranny by separating out different types of powers and assigning them to different and separate organs of government. This is the doctrine of the separation of powers, which, broadly speaking, demands, first, that each part of government should be separate and to an extent independent of the others, second, that each organ should be vested with only one main function of government, and third, that each should be able to check the actions of the others. (4) This is appropriately concise and to the point – the essay calls for a general appreciation of the constitution and, therefore, requires only light engagement with the separation of powers doctrine. This characteristic is, to a greater or lesser extent, apparent in every single liberal constitution and must, therefore, be seen as an essential aspect of such a constitution; again, it is implicit in Ridley’s thesis.
Implicit in all the above ideas is the notion that constitutions are in some way superior to and beyond government; they state what form the government shall take and what it may and may not do. They are above government in specifying matters that are prior to the formation or election of any government, and they also bind all governments. From this requirement there logically flows another, namely, that the constitution should be entrenched so that it is not readily alterable by the government of the day. As well as being logically necessary, this requirement is also practically necessary; if the constitution was not in some way entrenched, then any government could simply remove the limitations on its power that the constitution imposed and the basic idea of controlling the power of government would be lost.
We may now turn to the application of these ideas of constitutionalism to the UK. (5) It is good practice to divide the question into its essential requirements: this essay requires the student to demonstrate that they are familiar with the notion of a constitution and can apply this to the UK. Students often mix these requirements and, therefore, fail to develop one or the other strand. Laws may only be made through Acts of Parliament that comply with all specified formalities; resolutions of the Commons alone, for example, are not laws binding on the courts (Stockdale v Hansard (1839)). Furthermore, the courts enforce a basic notion of legality; government action impinging on citizens must be justified by reference to some law that empowers the specific act done, as in Entick v Carrington (1765). However, the ability of Parliament to enact what laws it pleases means that it can pass – and does increasingly pass – laws that give government very wide discretionary powers, so that it will be difficult for the courts to find that any particular actions are not justified in law. As to the notion of more substantive limitations on government rule in the form of entrenched rights, we may note immediately that there is no comprehensive system of entrenched rights, and orthodox constitutional doctrine tells us that Parliament is competent to legislate on any matter whatever. However, it has recently become apparent that the courts will not apply Acts of Parliament that conflict with rights deriving from European Community law (Factortame Ltd and Others v Secretary of State for Transport (No 2) (1991)), so that insofar as rights are protected by EU law, they do have a special status. However, EU law does not at present provide a set of basic civil and political rights. It should be noted that a few judges have recently, and mainly speaking extra-judicially, suggested that there may be basic rights and freedoms embedded in the common law, particularly the ability of the courts to engage in judicial review of executive action – a basic requirement of the rule of law – which the judges would not allow Parliament to remove.(6) Note the attempt to be precise at this point – often students of Constitutional Law are tempted to overstate the case in law, when in fact the position is more nuanced. The most notable recent example was an obiter comment by Lord Steyn in A-G v Jackson (2006) in which he stated that ‘an attempt to abolish judicial review or the ordinary role of the courts, the . . . House of Lords or a new Supreme Court may have to consider whether this is a constitutional fundamental which even a sovereign Parliament acting at the behest of a complaisant House of Commons cannot abolish’.(7) This demonstrates good use of recent authority.
Finally, what of the notion that the constitution must in some way be above or beyond the powers of government? One matter – parliamentary sovereignty itself – appears to be a matter of ‘higher law’, in that it is generally accepted that Parliament is unable to restrict its continuing sovereignty. This point has been thrown into some doubt as the courts have, in effect, allowed Parliament to restrict its own powers to legislate contrary to EU law. Nevertheless, there is little doubt that this restriction is ultimately one that Parliament could remove through withdrawal from the EU and probably also through the simple expedient of stating an express intention that a given Act should prevail over EU law. But, on the orthodox view, no other rule in the constitution is immune from change by an ordinary Act of Parliament, although, as just seen, there have been judicial hints that there are some fundamentals of the rule of law, in relation to which this may not be so. There is, of course, no authority, in terms of decided cases, for such a proposition. Thus, so called constitutional principles are in theory as readily changeable as rules relating to the licensing of public houses.(8) Note again that the legal rule is stated accurately setting up the more sophisticated analysis that follows. One caveat should be entered to this: the line of reasoning taken in Thoburn (2002) in relation to the refusal by the courts in Factortame to allow implied repeal to apply to the 1972 EC Act. In that case, Laws LJ held that, whilst Parliament could not bind itself in any way and had not done so in the 1972 Act, the courts could and should recognise certain Acts, including the 1972 Act, as ‘constitutional statutes’. Essentially these are those that affect fundamental rights or ‘the relationship between citizen and State in some general, overarching manner’.(9) Good use of statements made in Thoburn to develop the point. The legal consequence of recognising a statute as ‘constitutional’ was simple: ‘Ordinary statutes may be impliedly repealed. Constitutional statutes may not’. Whilst this view still allows for the unlimited sovereignty of Parliament when expressed through express repeal of a previous statute, however constitutionally significant, it does give a means of giving additional protection to constitutional fundamentals, although it is too early to say whether this revised view of sovereignty has won general acceptance amongst the senior judiciary.
Nevertheless, even under this view, Parliament could, at least theoretically, restrict the franchise, through express repeal of the Representation of the People Act (10) Again the point is well illustrated by reference to a specific example. and its replacement with a more restrictive statute, thus undermining even basic democratic principles. Hence, the basic notion, noted above, that the constitution should establish the source of governmental power and, in a democracy, establish that source as the people, is only partly fulfilled in the UK. The source of ultimate legal power in the UK is Parliament, not the people. Thus, the ‘no constitution’ thesis appears to be fairly readily made out, at least if it is taken to mean that ‘the constitution’ must consist of a form of ‘higher order’ law.(11) A clear conclusion made on the argument presented thus far.
How far has any of this changed in the UK following devolution and the advent of the HRA?(12) It is good policy to refer back to the question like this. The first point to make is that neither change has, in terms, created any ‘higher’ system of law. Both the Scotland Act and the HRA specifically affirm that they do not affect Parliament’s continued ability to reverse the changes they make, either wholly or in part. Thus, the HRA makes no attempt to entrench itself, and further provides quite specifically that if the courts find a piece of legislation, passed either before or after the HRA to be incompatible with one or more of the Convention rights, this will not affect the validity or continuing effect of that legislation (ss 3(2) and 4(6)). The White Paper on incorporation of the ECHR (Cm 3782) states quite clearly that the HRA is not intended to detract from the sovereignty of Parliament in any way. Similarly, the White Paper on Scottish devolution (Cm 3658) proclaims that ‘The United Kingdom is and will remain sovereign in all matters’, and this basic statement of principle is clearly enacted in the legislation. Section 28(7) of the Scotland Act states that the grant of legislative powers to the Scottish Parliament ‘does not affect the power of the United Kingdom Parliament to make law for Scotland’. Westminster may, therefore, still legislate in the devolved areas and may also repeal or modify the Scotland Act itself by ordinary legislation.(13) Good use of specific sections of the relevant Acts and attendant detail – this addresses the requirement of a detailed appreciation of these as indicated by their specific mention in the question.
These two pieces of legislation introduce substantive, rights-based limitations on governmental power (the HRA) and devolution of that power to a specified region (the Scotland Act). These are matters that, in most countries, would be part of ‘higher’ constitutional law, subject to change only through extraordinary procedures, themselves specified in the constitution. Instead, the opposite is provided for: following devolution and since the introduction of the HRA, Parliament is still, as a matter of law, able to invade basic rights or the legislative autonomy of Scotland as easily and readily as it may change the rate of income tax.
Thus, on one level, the ‘no constitution’ attack retains its basic force. But, on another level, its applicability to the UK has become more problematic.(14) The analysis is well structured here – it is clear that the straightforward point is concluded and the essay will now move on more detailed analysis of a more nuanced point. To take Scotland first, its Parliament and thus its government for most matters are now limited by what is in effect a codified constitution, made up of the Scotland Act itself, the ECHR and EU law. This is because the Scotland Act provides that Acts of the Scottish Parliament or Executive that are outside the powers devolved to it by the Act, or that infringe Convention rights or EU law, will be ultra vires (s 29), and further that the courts will have what can only be described as a power of constitutional review, being empowered to strike down legislation of the Scottish Parliament or actions of its Executive on those grounds. Entrenched matters are above and beyond the reach of the Scottish government and Parliament (since neither may alter the Scotland Act itself). Of course, the Westminster Parliament still has the theoretical right to legislate in the devolved areas against the will of the Scottish Parliament, and even to abolish the devolved institutions entirely, but no one seriously expects either to occur; the system would be unworkable if Westminster interfered in the devolved matters in this way, while the outright abolition of devolution has become virtually a political impossibility.
Turning to the HRA, we have noted that it is not in any formal way entrenched; nevertheless, for the first time, the rights of the UK citizenry have been authoritatively identified and stated to be fundamental. Executive actions are unlawful if they infringe such rights, unless primary legislation inescapably mandates or authorises the infringement (s 6). Daly (2001) confirms that this requires courts to assess for themselves whether Executive decisions have infringed Convention rights, affording a far higher level of protection for those rights than was available under judicial review, although there has been some vacillation about this point in some of the decided cases (see, for example, I. Leigh [2002] PL 265). For the first time, statutory construction fully and unequivocally recognises the importance of basic rights – courts have to read both past and future legislation into conformity with the Convention rights if possible (s 3(1)). Cases such as A (2001), Ghaidan v Mendoza (2004) and Secretary of State for the Home Department v AF (no 3) (2009) indicate the radical force of this provision, and how far it subordinates normal canons of statutory interpretation to the overriding imperative to uphold Convention rights if possible, though other cases, such as Re W and B, indicate a less activist approach. Ministers now have to make a statement when introducing legislation into Parliament that it does not infringe Convention rights, or that they believe it does, but they wish to proceed in any event (s 19).(15) A strong survey of the relevant cases on s3 – addressing the requirement in the question of a general overview of the court's response to the HRA.
Meanwhile, ambiguously worded legislation, which may infringe rights, can be dealt with via the interpretative obligation of the courts noted above. Together, and depending upon how rigorously the courts enforce the interpretative injunction in s 3(1) of the HRA (as indicated above, the cases to date indicate that it is being taken very seriously, though the outcomes vary), this adds up to quite a strong guarantee that legislation will no longer, in practice, infringe basic rights. All this, however, can be removed, simply by repeal of the HRA.
In conclusion, therefore, while no form of higher basic norms has, as a matter of law, been created, the effect of the canvassed reforms may in practice be indistinguishable. The basic ability of Parliament to remove so called constitutional guarantees, perhaps only by express repeal, will still remain, at least as a matter of strict law. However, Ridley’s suggestion that the concept of ‘constitutionalism’ at the normative, conventional level cannot be deployed in the UK will lose much of its force, as certain notions of devolved power at least attain an authoritatively declared basis and – as is likely – become fenced round by strong inhibitory conventions. In that sense, these reforms inject a modest dose of normative constitutionalism into the UK government and society, while leaving us formally still in search of a constitution.(16) An effective conclusion addressing the whole question directly.
Hide Content
The Fair
A number of commentators have argued that, in the only meaningful sense of the word, the UK has no constitution. Do you agree, and has this remained true following devolution to Scotland and the Human Rights Act 1998?
The UK may have no constitution because a constitution is more than simply a body of rules and arrangements that regulate the government of a country and its relations with its citizens (Ridley ((1988) 41 Parlt Aff 340) (1) While relevant, the use of this authority could be better explained. . This essay will consider in what way this is the case and discuss whether there is not a further definition of a constitution beyond that espoused by Ridley. This established, the essay will examine whether the introduction of devolution and the (at least, partial) incorporation of the ECHR via the HRA changes the conclusions previously reached on the UK Constitution. (2) A fair introduction setting out the structure of the essay.
A constitution must state what form the government shall take and what it may and may not do. This contains various notions, the first notion is a limited notion of government under law (Schauer (Playing by the Rules, 1991, pp 118–120). (3) This point could have been developed to describe its relationship with Ridley as set out in the introduction, and to demonstrate a greater understanding of what 'government under law' is. In the UK, government interference with individuals must be justified by reference to some law that empowers the specific act done, as in Entick v Carrington (1765), so in a limited sense the UK corresponds to aspects of this notion. Another notion is that of preventing a centralised dictatorship by separating out different types of powers and assigning them to different and separate organs of government – the doctrine of the separation of powers.
Under many constitutions (4) An example would benefit this point. there are some laws that the government cannot make at all; broadly, those which would infringe what are seen as fundamental human rights. Implicitly, that constitutions are in some way above government and, therefore, that the constitution should be entrenched,so that it is not readily alterable by the government of the day. Parliament is competent to legislate on any matter whatever. However, there is an exception for Acts of Parliament that conflict with rights deriving from European Community law (Factortame Ltd and Others v Secretary of State for Transport (No 2) (1991)), but EU law is far from a Bill of Rights at present. The HRA 1998 changed this situation in that it is a UK based statute enshrining certain basic rights and freedoms as set out in the ECHR. (5) The structure is rather messy at this point – it would be clearer to keep discussion of the attributes of a constitution, their application to the UK and the impact of the HRA separate. However, the HRA affirms that they do not affect Parliament’s ability to legislate contrary to the rights it contains (i.e. no entrenchment (ss 3 and 4)).
The only part of the UK ‘constitution’ of which this could be said is the principle of parliamentary sovereignty itself. (6) This point could be developed further. However, the operation of this doctrine is to deny the UK constitution, as so called constitutional principles are, in theory, as readily changeable as rules relating to the licensing of public houses; for example, Parliament could expressly repeal the Representation of the People Act (7) Good reference to a specific example. . (Although see the line of reasoning taken in Thoburn (2002) that the courts could and should recognise certain Acts, including the 1972 Act, as ‘constitutional statutes’.) (8) This is an important point and could have been further developed. As the source of ultimate legal power in the UK is Parliament, not the people, it is arguable that the UK does not have a constitution, as it does not even defend its supposedly founding principle of democracy.
The UK may, therefore, have a weak constitution (9) 'Weak' is rather vague. but commentators such as Ridley go too far in suggesting that the UK has no meaningful constitution at all, as there is a clear recognition that certain actions of government could be considered ‘unconstitutional’ in a normative and conventional sense. This has been strengthened by certain developments; the Scotland Act (s 29) provides that Acts of the Scottish Parliament or Executive that are outside the powers devolved to it by the Act, or that infringe Convention rights or EU law, will be ultra vires, and thus that the courts will have to engage in a type of constitutional review. However, the day to day experience of the Scottish people is now to live under a government that, in most areas, is constrained by a written constitution, which will protect basic rights, specify the electoral system and set the basic shape of government. Those entrenched matters are above and beyond the reach of the Scottish government and Parliament (since neither may alter the Scotland Act itself). As to Westminster, as devolution and the new Scottish government have become firmly entrenched, a convention has become established to the effect that the Westminster Parliament will not legislate in the devolved areas without the consent of the Scottish Parliament, just as such a convention developed during the period of the Stormont government of Northern Ireland between 1920 and 1972. (10) Good use of examples. This constitutional convention does not suffer from the indeterminacy of other, vaguer, conventions, such as the principle of individual and collective responsibility of government to Parliament, an indeterminacy that allows such principles to be manipulated by the government of the day and undercuts the confidence of any attempts to label a given act as clearly ‘unconstitutional’. This is because the Scotland Act lays down in considerable detail the reserved powers of Westminster and, thus, the powers devolved. Devolution has thus become ‘constitutionalised’.
In conclusion, therefore, while Parliament is strictly legally able to remove constitutional guarantees, perhaps only by express repeal, the suggestion that the concept of ‘constitutionalism’ at the normative, conventional level is inapplicable to the UK is inaccurate and the HRA and Scotland Act confirm this. (11) A fairly effective conclusion albeit rather brief.
Hide Content
The Ugly
A number of commentators have argued that, in the only meaningful sense of the word, the UK has no constitution. Do you agree, and has this remained true following devolution to Scotland and the Human Rights Act 1998?
The Scotland Act and the HRA do not affect Parliament’s ability to enact legislation and are unentrenched. (1) This is a poor beginning as it says nothing about the structure of the essay and says nothing of the meaning of a constitution, which is essential to the question. This means that the doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty remains intact. If the courts find a piece of legislation, passed either before or after the HRA to be incompatible with one or more of the Convention rights, this will not affect the validity or continuing effect of that legislation (ss 3(2) and 4(6)). Parliamentary sovereignty is the UK constitution (2) This is an overstatement and reflects only one view of the constitution, which demonstrates that the student has not appreciated a range of views on the constitution as required. and, therefore, it is technically incorrect to say that the UK has no constitution; however, the HRA and Scotland Act are strong instances of conventional and normative limits to the power of Parliament, because as regards Scotland, the Scottish Parliament and government are limited by the Scotland Act itself, the ECHR and EU law,while, as regards the HRA, the rights of UK citizens are authoritatively identified and stated to be fundamental, and executive actions are unlawful if they infringe such rights, unless primary legislation inescapably mandates or authorises the infringement. (3) While there are some good points here they are rather jumbled and incoherent, which obstructs the analysis.
The Scotland Act helps answer the English question, which arises because there is no UK Constitution and because the UK Parliament, as a result, has to serve as the Parliament for England, but with the problematic feature of containing a significant proportion of MPs from the non-English nations. Out of a total of 646 MPs, 117 represent non-English constituents: Scotland has 59 (a number recently reduced from 72 in partial recognition of the English question), Wales has 40 and Northern Ireland has 18. There are two distinct consequences that follow from this: first, what might be termed the government-formation issue; second, the legislation-legitimacy issue. As to the first, the problem is simply that it is possible that, in future, there will be a UK government that only holds power due to the presence in Westminster, as part of the governing party’s majority, of Scottish and Welsh MPs (hereafter the ‘Celtic MPs’). There would be nothing wrong with such a situation, save for the fact that the UK government also has to act as the English government (since there is no other). Thus the English people face the possible future of being governed by an administration that is a minority one in terms of seats: in blunt terms, by a Labour government when they voted Conservative. (4) This is clearly irrelevant information – a common error in student essays associated with poor revision is to introduce irrelevant analysis.
So, in some ways, the UK does have a constitution, but it is not based on Parliamentary Sovereignty. Before the HRA and Scotland Act this was not so much (5) This is rather vague. the case although government interference required authorisation the government could always enact legislation (6) This is obviously incorrect – Parliament enacts legislation. to give it a wide discretion. Also courts will not apply Acts of Parliament that conflict with rights deriving from European Community law. (7) The relevance of this requires some explanation and the case of Factortame Ltd and Others v Secretary of State for Transport (No 2) (1991) should be referred to. Furthermore some judges uphold basic rights and freedoms as part of the common law (e.g. judicial review of executive action) – a basic requirement of the rule of law – which the judges would not allow Parliament to remove. Also Parliament is not always considered supreme because the Courts could refuse to apply the doctrine of implied repeal, as they do in relation to ‘constitutional statutes’ (Thoburn (2002)). (8) This point also requires an explanation of implied repeal, as it relates to parliamentary sovereignty. Even though the HRA is not entrenched, for the first time courts have to read both past and future legislation into conformity with the Convention rights if possible (s 3(1)); see also A (2001), Ghaidan v Mendoza (2004) and Secretary of State for the Home Department v AF (no 3) (2009). So, in conclusion, the effect of the HRA and Scotland Act is not to create a British constitution, as they do not affect the ability of Parliament to repeal ‘constitutional guarantees’, even if they do strengthen normative constitutionalism. (9) A very basic conclusion that doesn't entirely reflect the analysis.
Hide Content
Hide Content
Lawcards
Revision Checklist
Chapter 1: Introduction;
- The purpose of a constitution
- How constitutions are defined
- The differences between written and unwritten constitutions
- The characteristics of the UK constitution
- Sources of the constitution
- Legal sources
- Non-legal sources including conventions
Chapter 2: Fundamental concepts underlying the constitution;
- Fundamental concept: Rule of law
- Fundamental concept: Separation of powers
- Fundamental concept: Parliamentary sovereignty including EU law
Chapter 3: The executive;
- The function of central government
- The exercising of executive power
- The role and scope of collective ministerial responsibility
- The role and scope of individual ministerial responsibility
Chapter 4: The legislature;
- The function of the House of Commons
- The legislative process
- Scrutiny of the executive by the Legislature
- The function of the House of Lords
- The reform process of the House of Lords
- Devolution of power to the countries of the Union
- The nature of electoral law in the UK
- The different voting systems used and available for use
- The scope of parliamentary privilege
- The range of parliamentary standards
Chapter 5: Human rights and civil liberties;
- The historical protection of fundamental rights and liberties
- The nature of residual rights and its contemporary relevance in the UK
- The role and function of the European Convention on Human Rights
- The Human Rights Act 1998 and the arrival of positive rights
- How to raise Convention rights under the Human Rights Act 1998
- The scope of rights restricted by statute and the common law
Chapter 6: The Royal Prerogative;
- The concept of the royal prerogative
- Examples of prerogative
- Judicial Control of the prerogative
- GCHQ Case
Chapter 7: Introduction to administrative law;
- The role and function of judicial review
- The distinction between review and appeal
- The threefold classification for judicial review
- Who can apply for judicial review?
- The remedies available in judicial review
Hide Content
Glossary
Click on the glossary term to see the definition
Chapter 1
- Authoritative textbooks
- this is one of the sources of the constitution. They are a non-legal source. An example would be An Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution by AV Dicey (1885
- Case law
- this is one of the sources of the constitution. Cases are heard by the judiciary which then produces precedent which then provides us with the definition of the relationship between the institutions of state and between the state and the individual.
- Constitution
- this is a single document or series of documents or written and unwritten rules which contain either the basic rules of state or determine the creation and operation of governmental institutions.
- Convention
- this is an unwritten obligation which is central to the effective operation of the constitution. The most important convention in the UK is Ministerial Responsibility which plays an important role in providing guidance as to how the executive personnel should work.
- Decision
- is a source of EC law. It is a decision of the European Court of Justice. It shall be binding in its entirety upon those to whom it is addressed.
- Legislation
- this is one of the sources of the constitution. It is an Act of Parliament and examples relevant to Constitutional law would include the Human Rights Act 1998.
Chapter 2
- Express and Implied Repeal
- this is one of the features of the doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty. So that Parliament can retain its continuing sovereignty Parliament cannot bind future Parliaments. To avoid questions of supremacy if one Act of Parliament contradicts an earlier Act of Parliament then it will be assumed by the courts that the latter Act apples. This is known as implied repeal. If an Act of Parliament explicitly states that an earlier Act of Parliament has been repealed then this is an example of Express repeal.
- Justiciability
- this is a principle most commonly identified with the decision in Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister of State for the Civil Service (GCHQ case) (1985) where the exercising of prerogative powers was considered. In this case the House of Lords decided that the exercising of some prerogative powers could be reviewed by the courts. These powers would be justiciable, or subject to adjudication. Some of the prerogative powers (relating to national security) would not be capable of adjudication and these are termed non-justiciable.
- Parliamentary Sovereignty
- this is possibly the most important doctrine of Constitutional law in the UK. It confirms that the source of ultimate authority in the UK is Parliament rather than, as in the US, a constitution. At its core the doctrine states that Parliament can legislate on any topic, it cannot bind future Parliaments or be bound by its predecessors and no one can challenge the validity of an Act of Parliament. It is seen as the cornerstone of the UK constitution and it is the most democratic of doctrines because those who make most of the important decisions (House of Commons) are made by those who have been elected by the people.
- Royal Prerogative
- this is an ancient source of the UK Constitution. There exist powers which the executive can exercise without the passage of legislation. Such powers are common to all constitutions but are termed part of the Royal Prerogative because the UK constitution is monarchical in character. Historically these powers were actually exercised by the Monarch in accordance with their pre-eminence and dignity. In the UK today these powers are often exercised in the name of the Monarch by members of the executive. These powers include a declaration of war and the granting of honours.
- Rule of Law
- like Parliamentary Sovereignty and the Royal Prerogative this is a fundamental principle of the UK Constitution. It is an aspiration of all constitutions where its essence is that no man is above the law and all individuals should be equal to others and not subject to arbitrary rule. In the UK Constitution the rule of law is most commonly associated with AV Dicey in his An Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (1885).
- Separation of Powers
-
this is one of the fundamental principles of all constitutions. It is the idea that there should be a clear demarcation in function between each of the three organs of state (executive, legislature and judiciary) and the powers of each should be held in check by the others.
In the UK the separation is often described as a fusion because of the incidence of overlap between these organs. These overlaps are regularly controlled by constitutional conventions.
- Attribution of Powers
- this is one of the legal doctrines of EC law which states that the Community is only entitled to act when it is given the express power to do so.
- Directive
- this is a secondary source of EC law. It is a form of legislation. It shall be binding, as to the result to be achieved, upon each Member State to which it is addressed, but shall leave to the national authorities the choice of form and methods. It is the most common form of legislation.
- Proportionality
- this is one of the legal doctrines of EC law which states that the measure of Community action must be in proportion to the objective being pursued.
- Regulation
- this is a secondary source of EC law. It is a form of legislation. It shall have general application and shall be binding in its entirety and directly applicable in all Member States.
- Subsidiarity
- this is one of the legal doctrines of EC law which states that the Community not only has to show that it has the power to act but must justify why it and not the Member State should act.
- Supremacy (EC)
- this is a doctrine which has been developed by the European Court of Justice. It emerges in the case of Costa v Enel (1964) and the ECJ takes the view that Member States have limited their sovereignty, in areas of EC law, as a result of their entering into the EC Treaty, as amended.
- Treaties (EC)
- these are the primary and most important sources of EC law. The treaties, as amended, outline the framework under which the Community and Union operate. For example Article 234 EC Treaty provides for the ECJ as final arbiter on Community law.
Chapter Three
- Cabinet
- this is the committee at the heart of the executive. It is the supreme decision making body in government. Members of the Cabinet are appointed by the monarch on the advice of the Prime Minister.
- Collective Ministerial Responsibility
- this is one of the central conventions which ensure executive accountability to Parliament. Its basic tenets are that government must speak with one voice. Cabinet discussions are confidential and the government must collectively resign if it loses a confidence vote in the House of Commons.
- Confidence rule
- this is where a government loses a tabled vote of no confidence and the Prime Minister is required to resign and seek the dissolution of Parliament. Today these are rare and the last government to be removed by a vote of no confidence was that of James Callaghan in 1979.
- Individual Ministerial Responsibility
- this is one of the central conventions which ensure executive accountability to Parliament. Its basic tenets are that a Minister may resign if they are seen to be responsible for a policy failure within their ministry but not for an operational failure within their ministry. They may also resign for personal indiscretions. It would appear that this convention no longer contains an absolute obligation to resign. It will depend on the circumstances of each case.
- Prime Minister
- this is the most senior member of the Cabinet in the executive branch of government. The Prime Minister is appointed by the monarch according to the constitutional convention that the monarch must appoint the MP who is best able to command a stable majority.
Chapter Four
- Devolution
- this is the process by which government power has been gradually devolved from Westminster to Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland since 1998. Parliament at Westminster does still retain its ultimate sovereignty over these devolved governments.
- House of Commons
- this is the elected, and therefore most powerful, chamber of Parliament in the UK. It is based in Westminster.
- House of Lords
- this is the unelected, and therefore least powerful, chamber of Parliament in the UK. It is based in Westminster.
- Parliament
- for the purposes of Constitutional law, Parliament consists of the House of Commons, the House of Lords and the Monarch.
- Parliamentary Privilege
- in line with the doctrine of Parliamentary Sovereignty both Houses of Parliament (House of Commons and House of Lords) enjoy member privileges in order to discharge their functions. Examples of these privileges include freedom of speech, freedom to regulate their own composition and freedom to regulate their own proceedings.
- Select Committee
- this is usually also known as a Commons select committee and it is generally responsible for overseeing the work of government agencies or departments. Their composition remains constant during any one Parliament.
- Standing Committee
- this is a committee which is also known as a public bill committee. They are responsible for scrutinising proposed legislation in order to improve its quality. They only last for the duration of the Bill.
Chapter Five
- Declaration of Incompatibility
- this is where a higher court signals to the Government that provision of legislation is incompatible with the European Convention on Human Rights. Its authority comes from s4 Human Rights Act 1998.
- Derogation
-
this is enshrined in Article 15 of the European Convention on Human Rights and is therefore giving effect by the Human Rights Act 1998. It permits contracting parties (member states) to derogate from convention rights in times of war or public emergency. It has proved a popular tool for governments in their fight against terrorism. The House of Lords have been careful to ensure it is not used (or abused) lightly. See A v Secretary of State for the Home Department (2005).
Freedom of Association and Assembly: this is the right citizens have to associate and assemble. This right is enshrined in Article 11 of the European Convention on Human Rights and so given effect by the Human Rights Act 1998. The right is qualified and so can be restricted if it is in the public interest to do so. There also exist common law limitations to this right on the basis that someone is committing or threatening to commit a breach of the peace. Legislation (Public Order Act 1986) exists to limit the right to free assembly. Finally the Terrorism Act 2000 limits the freedom to associate by identifying proscribed organisations which citizens are not permitted to associate with.
Freedom of Expression: this is the right citizens have to free speech. This right is enshrined in Article 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights and so given effect by the Human Rights Act 1998. The right is qualified and so can be restricted if it is in the public interest to do so. The grounds for restriction include national security, censorship, contempt of court, defamation, public order and privacy.
- National Security
- this is one of the reasons why the State justifies interference with an individual's rights and freedoms.
- Official Secrecy
- this is one of the reasons why the State justified interference with an individual's freedom of expression.
- Police Powers
- these are the powers that are enjoyed by the police in their official capacity. These powers can involve the curtailing of individual liberties. Most of these powers can now be found in the Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984.
Chapter Six
- Royal Prerogative
- this is an ancient source of the UK Constitution. There exist powers which the executive can exercise without the passage of legislation. Such powers are common to all constitutions but are termed part of the Royal Prerogative because the UK constitution is monarchical in character. Historically these powers were actually exercised by the Monarch in accordance with their pre-eminence and dignity. In the UK today these powers are often exercised in the name of the Monarch by members of the executive. These powers include a declaration of war and the granting of honours.
Chapter Seven
- Exclusivity principle
- this is a principle which was confirmed in the case of O'Reilly v Mackman (1983). It states that a distinction between public and private law must be made in respect of questioning the decisions made by statutory bodies. If an individual tries to use a private action to challenge a decision by a public body then this would amount to an abuse of process. This principle has been criticised on the basis that meritorious cases have been struck out on purely procedure grounds.
- Illegality
- this is one of the three grounds for judicial review as classified by Lord Diplock in Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister of State for the Civil Service (GCHQ case) (1985). It embraces a number of different reasons upon which a public body will be subject to judicial review. This includes where the public body exceeds their jurisdiction, fails to direct itself correctly in law, fails to fulfil a statutory duty, acts for an improper purpose, fails to take into account all relevant considerations, unlawfully delegates discretionary powers to another, fetters its discretion and excessively interferes with fundamental rights. It is often called the doctrine of ultra vires.
- Irrationality
- this is one of the three grounds for judicial review as classified by Lord Diplock in Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister of State for the Civil Service (GCHQ case) (1985). A decision of a public authority will be open to challenge on this ground if the court is satisfied that the decision is so unreasonable that no authority could ever come to it or so absurd that no sensible person could ever dream that it law within the powers of the authority. It is often termed the Wednesbury principle after the decision in Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation (1948). Since the Human Rights Act 1998 came into force it has also embraced the proportionality test. Some commentators believe that over time the concept of irrationality will be eclipsed by the much wider test of proportionality in judicial review proceedings.
- Judicial Review
- this is the process by which the courts exercise a supervisory role over the acts and omissions of public bodies. The process is not the same as an ordinary appeal. The court is not interested in the merits of the decision. They are concerned with the decision making process.
- Legitimate expectation
- this is one of the principles embraced in the 'procedural impropriety' ground of judicial review. Here a person may have a legitimate expectation that they will be given a hearing, or consulted before a decision is taken. This is usually because they have relied on a previous course of conduct to that effect.
- Natural Justice
- this is one of the principles embraced in the 'procedural impropriety' ground of judicial review. It broadly covers three fundamental principles. The first is that no man is to be a judge in his own cause. The second is that no man is to be condemned unheard. The third is that a decision maker has a general duty to act fairly.
- Ouster clause
- this is a clause in a statute which attempts to 'oust' the jurisdiction of the court. Given that these clauses try to exclude review by the courts they have construed them strictly. See Anisminic Ltd v Foreign Compensation Commission (1969).
- Procedural impropriety
- this is one of the three grounds for judicial review as classified by Lord Diplock in Council of Civil Service Unions v Minister of State for the Civil Service (GCHQ case) (1985). The key elements of procedural impropriety comprise where there has been a breach of natural justice, procedural unfairness, and failure to comply with statutory procedural obligations and where an applicant's legitimate expectation has been undermined.
- Rule against bias
- this is one of the principles embraced in the 'procedural impropriety' ground of judicial review. It means that any decision maker must not have or must not be seen to have any pecuniary, family or professional interest in the outcome of any decision.